Options

Lecture 57 - Chapter 4: Feasibility Relations

edited February 2020 in Baez ACT 2019: Lectures

Let's look at some examples of feasibility relations!

Feasibility relations work between preorders, but for simplicity suppose we have two posets \(X\) and \(Y\). We can draw them using Hasse diagrams:

image

Here an arrow means that one element is less than or equal to another: for example, the arrow \(S \to W\) means that \(S \le W\). But we don't bother to draw all possible inequalities as arrows, just the bare minimum. For example, obviously \(S \le S\) by reflexivity, but we don't bother to draw arrows from each element to itself. Also \(S \le N\) follows from \(S \le E\) and \(E \le N\) by transitivity, but we don't bother to draw arrows that follow from others using transitivity. This reduces clutter.

(Usually in a Hasse diagram we draw bigger elements near the top, but notice that \(e \in Y\) is not bigger than the other elements of \(Y\). In fact it's neither \(\ge\) or \(\le\) any other elements of \(Y\) - it's just floating in space all by itself. That's perfectly allowed in a poset.)

Now, we saw that a feasibility relation from \(X\) to \(Y\) is a special sort of relation from \(X\) to \(Y\). We can think of a relation from \(X\) to \(Y\) as a function \(\Phi\) for which \(\Phi(x,y)\) is either \(\text{true}\) or \(\text{false}\) for each pair of elements \( x \in X, y \in Y\). Then a feasibility relation is a relation such that:

  1. If \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\) and \(x' \le x\) then \(\Phi(x',y) = \text{true}\).

  2. If \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\) and \(y \le y'\) then \(\Phi(x,y') = \text{true}\).

Fong and Spivak have a cute trick for drawing feasibility relations: when they draw a blue dashed arrow from \(x \in X\) to \(y \in Y\) it means \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\). But again, they leave out blue dashed arrows that would follow from rules 1 and 2, to reduce clutter!

Let's do an example:

image

So, we see \(\Phi(E,b) = \text{true}\). But we can use the two rules to draw further conclusions from this:

  • Since \(\Phi(E,b) = \text{true}\) and \(S \le E\) then \(\Phi(S,b) = \text{true}\), by rule 1.

  • Since \(\Phi(S,b) = \text{true}\) and \(b \le d\) then \(\Phi(S,d) = \text{true}\), by rule 2.

and so on.

Puzzle 171. Is \(\Phi(E,c) = \text{true}\) ?

Puzzle 172. Is \(\Phi(E,e) = \text{true}\)?

I hope you get the idea! We can think of the arrows in our Hasse diagrams as one-way streets going between cities in two countries, \(X\) and \(Y\). And we can think of the blue dashed arrows as one-way plane flights from cities in \(X\) to cities in \(Y\). Then \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\) if we can get from \(x \in X\) to \(y \in Y\) using any combination of streets and plane flights!

That's one reason \(\Phi\) is called a feasibility relation.

What's cool is that rules 1 and 2 can also be expressed by saying

$$ \Phi : X^{\text{op}} \times Y \to \mathbf{Bool} $$ is a monotone function. And it's especially cool that we need the '\(\text{op}\)' over the \(X\). Make sure you understand that: the \(\text{op}\) over the \(X\) but not the \(Y\) is why we can drive to an airport in \(X\), then take a plane, then drive from an airport in \(Y\).

Here are some ways to lots of feasibility relations. Suppose \(X\) and \(Y\) are preorders.

Puzzle 173. Suppose \(f : X \to Y \) is a monotone function from \(X\) to \(Y\). Prove that there is a feasibility relation \(\Phi\) from \(X\) to \(Y\) given by

$$ \Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y .$$ Puzzle 174. Suppose \(g: Y \to X \) is a monotone function from \(Y\) to \(X\). Prove that there is a feasibility relation \(\Psi\) from \(X\) to \(Y\) given by

$$ \Psi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } x \le g(y) .$$ Puzzle 175. Suppose \(f : X \to Y\) and \(g : Y \to X\) are monotone functions, and use them to build feasibility relations \(\Phi\) and \(\Psi\) as in the previous two puzzles. When is

$$ \Phi = \Psi ? $$ To read other lectures go here.

Comments

  • 1.
    edited July 2018

    Puzzle 171. Is \(\Phi(E,c) = \text{true}\) ?

    No (if I am reading the diagram correctly)

    Puzzle 172. Is \(\Phi(E,e) = \text{true}\)?

    Yes

    We have \(E \leq N\) so \(\Phi(N,e) \leq \Phi(E,e)\). Since the diagram indicates \(\Phi(N,e)=\text{true}\) then we know \(\Phi(E,e) = \text{true}\).

    Puzzle 175. Suppose \(f : X \to Y\) and \(g : Y \to X\) are monotone functions, and use them to build feasibility relations \(\Phi\) and \(\Psi\) as in the previous two puzzles. When is

    $$ \Phi = \Psi ? $$

    When \(f\) and \(g\) are adjoints, that is to say \(f \dashv g\)

    Comment Source:> **Puzzle 171.** Is \\(\Phi(E,c) = \text{true}\\) ? **No** (if I am reading the diagram correctly) > **Puzzle 172.** Is \\(\Phi(E,e) = \text{true}\\)? **Yes** We have \\(E \leq N\\) so \\(\Phi(N,e) \leq \Phi(E,e)\\). Since the diagram indicates \\(\Phi(N,e)=\text{true}\\) then we know \\(\Phi(E,e) = \text{true}\\). > **Puzzle 175.** Suppose \\(f : X \to Y\\) and \\(g : Y \to X\\) are monotone functions, and use them to build feasibility relations \\(\Phi\\) and \\(\Psi\\) as in the previous two puzzles. When is > > \[ \Phi = \Psi ? \] When \\(f\\) and \\(g\\) are adjoints, that is to say \\(f \dashv g\\)
  • 2.
    edited July 2018

    Puzzle 173

    If we let \(y = f(x')\) then \(f(x) \leq y\) sets up the following inequalities by definition of a monotone function :

    $$x \leq x' \;\text{and}\; f(x) \leq f(x')$$ By definition of a feasibility relation the above inequality implies :

    $$\Phi(x,f(x)) \;\text{implies}\; \Phi(x',f(x'))$$ So...

    $$\text{If} \; \Phi(x,f(x)) = \text{true and} \; f(x) \leq y, \text{then} \; \Phi(x,y) = \text{true}$$ Puzzle 174

    Similarly,

    $$\text{If} \; \Psi(g(y),y) = \text{true and} \; x \leq g(y), \text{then} \; \Psi(x,y) = \text{true}$$

    Comment Source:**Puzzle 173** If we let \\(y = f(x')\\) then \\(f(x) \leq y\\) sets up the following inequalities by definition of a monotone function : $$x \leq x' \;\text{and}\; f(x) \leq f(x')$$ By definition of a feasibility relation the above inequality implies : $$\Phi(x,f(x)) \;\text{implies}\; \Phi(x',f(x'))$$ So... $$\text{If} \; \Phi(x,f(x)) = \text{true and} \; f(x) \leq y, \text{then} \; \Phi(x,y) = \text{true}$$ **Puzzle 174** Similarly, $$\text{If} \; \Psi(g(y),y) = \text{true and} \; x \leq g(y), \text{then} \; \Psi(x,y) = \text{true}$$
  • 3.
    edited July 2018

    Puzzle 174: Given \(g : Y -> X\) and \(\Psi(x,y) = x \le g(y)\), we must show that \(\Psi\) is a feasibility relation. \( \Psi \) is a feasibility relation if and only if \[\forall x',x : X, y,y' : Y, x'\le x, y \le y', \Psi(x,y) \to \Psi(x',y')\] \(\Psi(x,y)\) equals, by the definition of Psi: \[x \le g(y)\] By transitivity and \(x\le x'\): \[x'\le g(y)\] By monotonicity we have \[y\le y' \to g(y)\le g(y')\] and so \[\to x'\le g(y')\] which by definition of \(\Psi\), equals \(\Psi(x',y')\) Therefor, \[\Psi(x,y) \to \Psi(x',y')\] QED.

    Comment Source:Puzzle 174: Given \\(g : Y -> X\\) and \\(\Psi(x,y) = x \le g(y)\\), we must show that \\(\Psi\\) is a feasibility relation. \\( \Psi \\) is a feasibility relation if and only if \\[\forall x',x : X, y,y' : Y, x'\le x, y \le y', \Psi(x,y) \to \Psi(x',y')\\] \\(\Psi(x,y)\\) equals, by the definition of Psi: \\[x \le g(y)\\] By transitivity and \\(x\le x'\\): \\[x'\le g(y)\\] By monotonicity we have \\[y\le y' \to g(y)\le g(y')\\] and so \\[\to x'\le g(y')\\] which by definition of \\(\Psi\\), equals \\(\Psi(x',y')\\) Therefor, \\[\Psi(x,y) \to \Psi(x',y')\\] QED.
  • 4.
    edited July 2018

    @Matthew – I agree with your answers to 172 and 175 but surely we do have \(\Phi(E,c) = \text{true}\) because we can "drive" from \(E\) to \(N\) and then "fly" from \(N\) to \(c\).

    Comment Source:@Matthew – I agree with your answers to **172** and **175** but surely we do have \\(\Phi(E,c) = \text{true}\\) because we can "drive" from \\(E\\) to \\(N\\) and then "fly" from \\(N\\) to \\(c\\).
  • 5.

    Anindya wrote

    surely we do have \(\Phi(E,c) = \text{true}\) because we can "drive" from \(E\) to \(N\) and then "fly" from \(N\) to \(c\).

    Yeah, you are right. I read the diagram incorrectly... thanks!

    Comment Source:[Anindya wrote](https://forum.azimuthproject.org/discussion/comment/19964/#Comment_19964×) > surely we do have \\(\Phi(E,c) = \text{true}\\) because we can "drive" from \\(E\\) to \\(N\\) and then "fly" from \\(N\\) to \\(c\\). Yeah, you are right. I read the diagram incorrectly... thanks!
  • 6.

    Anindya Bhattacharyya wrote:

    @Matthew – I agree with your answers to 172 and 175 but surely we do have \(\Phi(E,c) = \text{true}\) because we can "drive" from \(E\) to \(N\) and then "fly" from \(N\) to \(c\).

    Yeah, I was thinking the same thing.

    Comment Source:Anindya Bhattacharyya wrote: >@Matthew – I agree with your answers to **172** and **175** but surely we do have \\(\Phi(E,c) = \text{true}\\) because we can "drive" from \\(E\\) to \\(N\\) and then "fly" from \\(N\\) to \\(c\\). Yeah, I was thinking the same thing.
  • 7.

    In some sense, in the pictures it would be more sensible to put \(Y\) on top of \(X\). One can think (sometimes usefully, sometimes less usefully) of a feasability relation (or profunctor) between preorders as giving rise to a new preorder, known as the collage. The underlying set of the collage is the disjoint union \(X \sqcup Y\) and on both \(X\) and \(Y\) the new preorder restricts to the preorders you started with, but for all \(x \in X\) and \(y \in Y\) you have \(y\not\le x\) whilst \(x\le y\, \iff\ \Phi(x,y)\).

    The pictures drawn with the blue arrows are the Hasse diagrams of these collages. Nothing in \(Y\) ever comes before anything in \(X\) in this preorder, so that's why it would make sense to draw \(Y\) on top of \(X\). I'll leave it for someone to produce such a version of the examples above :-).

    Comment Source:In some sense, in the pictures it would be more sensible to put \\(Y\\) *on top of* \\(X\\). One can think (sometimes usefully, sometimes less usefully) of a feasability relation (or profunctor) between preorders as giving rise to a new preorder, known as the **collage**. The underlying set of the collage is the disjoint union \\(X \sqcup Y\\) and on both \\(X\\) and \\(Y\\) the new preorder restricts to the preorders you started with, but for all \\(x \in X\\) and \\(y \in Y\\) you have \\(y\not\le x\\) whilst \\(x\le y\, \iff\ \Phi(x,y)\\). The pictures drawn with the blue arrows are the Hasse diagrams of these collages. Nothing in \\(Y\\) ever comes before anything in \\(X\\) in this preorder, so that's why it would make sense to draw \\(Y\\) on top of \\(X\\). I'll leave it for someone to produce such a version of the examples above :-).
  • 8.

    Puzzle 171. Yes, \(\Phi(E,c) = \text{true}\) because we can first walk from \(E\) to \(N\) and then fly from \(N\) to \(c\). I hadn't noticed this when creating this puzzle! Like Matthew, I thought the answer was \(\text{false}\).

    Puzzle 172. Yes, \(\Phi(E,e) = \text{true}\) because we can first walk from \(E\) to \(N\) and then fly from \(N\) to \(e\).

    I should have given an example that was a bit different, like \(\Phi(S,d)\).

    Comment Source:**Puzzle 171.** Yes, \\(\Phi(E,c) = \text{true}\\) because we can first walk from \\(E\\) to \\(N\\) and then fly from \\(N\\) to \\(c\\). I hadn't noticed this when creating this puzzle! Like Matthew, I thought the answer was \\(\text{false}\\). **Puzzle 172.** Yes, \\(\Phi(E,e) = \text{true}\\) because we can first walk from \\(E\\) to \\(N\\) and then fly from \\(N\\) to \\(e\\). I should have given an example that was a bit different, like \\(\Phi(S,d)\\).
  • 9.
    edited July 2018

    Michael wrote:

    Puzzle 173. If we let \(y = f(x')\) then \(f(x) \leq y\) sets up the following inequalities by definition of a monotone function :

    $$x \leq x' \;\text{and}\; f(x) \leq f(x')$$ By definition of a feasibility relation the above inequality implies : $$\Phi(x,f(x)) \;\text{implies}\; \Phi(x',f(x'))$$ So... $$\text{If} \; \Phi(x,f(x)) = \text{true and} \; f(x) \leq y, \text{then} \; \Phi(x,y) = \text{true}$$

    I have trouble following what you're doing here. The question asks you to assume \(\Phi\) is defined by

    $$ \Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y .$$ where \(f\) is monotone, and prove that \(\Phi\) is a feasibility relation.

    So, it makes me very nervous when you say "by the definition of a feasibility relation the above inequality implies...." That sounds like you are assuming \(\Phi\) is a feasibility relation and deducing things from this. But this is what you're trying to prove.

    It's quite possible you have a good idea and I'm getting stumped by the way you're explaining it. Here's how a mathematician would start an answer to this puzzle:

    Assume \(f : X \to Y\) is monotone and define \(\Phi\) by

    $$ \Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y .$$ We want to prove \(\Phi\) is a feasibility relation. So, it suffices to show
    1. If \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\) and \(x' \le x\) then \(\Phi(x',y) = \text{true}\).
    2. If \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\) and \(y \le y'\) then \(\Phi(x,y') = \text{true}\).

    In other words: state what you're assuming and what you're trying to show. Then use the assumptions to get what you're trying to show.

    Another fine approach starts with the original definition of feasibility relation:

    Assume \(f : X \to Y\) is monotone and define \(\Phi\) by

    $$ \Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y .$$ We want to prove \(\Phi\) is a feasibility relation. So, it suffices to show that if \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\) and \(x' \le x\) and \(y \le y'\), then \(\Phi(x',y') = \text{true}\).
    Comment Source:Michael wrote: > **Puzzle 173.** If we let \\(y = f(x')\\) then \\(f(x) \leq y\\) sets up the following inequalities by definition of a monotone function : > $$x \leq x' \;\text{and}\; f(x) \leq f(x')$$ > By definition of a feasibility relation the above inequality implies : > $$\Phi(x,f(x)) \;\text{implies}\; \Phi(x',f(x'))$$ > So... > $$\text{If} \; \Phi(x,f(x)) = \text{true and} \; f(x) \leq y, \text{then} \; \Phi(x,y) = \text{true}$$ I have trouble following what you're doing here. The question asks you to _assume_ \\(\Phi\\) is defined by \[ \Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y .\] where \\(f\\) is monotone, and _prove_ that \\(\Phi\\) is a feasibility relation. So, it makes me very nervous when you say "by the definition of a feasibility relation the above inequality implies...." That sounds like you are _assuming_ \\(\Phi\\) is a feasibility relation and deducing things from this. But this is what you're trying to _prove_. It's quite possible you have a good idea and I'm getting stumped by the way you're explaining it. Here's how a mathematician would start an answer to this puzzle: > Assume \\(f : X \to Y\\) is monotone and define \\(\Phi\\) by > \[ \Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y .\] > We want to prove \\(\Phi\\) is a feasibility relation. So, it suffices to show > 1. If \\(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\\) and \\(x' \le x\\) then \\(\Phi(x',y) = \text{true}\\). > 2. If \\(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\\) and \\(y \le y'\\) then \\(\Phi(x,y') = \text{true}\\). In other words: state what you're assuming and what you're trying to show. Then use the assumptions to get what you're trying to show. Another fine approach starts with the original definition of feasibility relation: > Assume \\(f : X \to Y\\) is monotone and define \\(\Phi\\) by > \[ \Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y .\] > We want to prove \\(\Phi\\) is a feasibility relation. So, it suffices to show that if \\(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\\) and \\(x' \le x\\) and \\(y \le y'\\), then \\(\Phi(x',y') = \text{true}\\).
  • 10.
    edited July 2018

    Simon wrote:

    One can think (sometimes usefully, sometimes less usefully) of a feasability relation (or profunctor) between preorders as giving rise to a new preorder, known as the collage. The underlying set of the collage is the disjoint union \(X \sqcup Y\) and on both \(X\) and \(Y\) the new preorder restricts to the preorders you started with, but for all \(x \in X\) and \(y \in Y\) you have \(y\not\le x\) whilst \(x\le y\, \iff\ \Phi(x,y)\).

    I think it's really great how one can glom together two preorders into a "collage" this way using a feasibility relation... or more generally, glom together two categories using profunctor. But the preorder case is so easy to visualize and like!

    image

    I got interested in collages when thinking about the 10-fold way in condensed matter physics. I noticed that it arose from taking the 2-element super-Brauer group of the complex numbers and the 8-element super-Brauer group of the real numbers and glomming them into a single structure. It's easy to check that a field homomorphism like \(\mathbb{R} \hookrightarrow \mathbb{C}\) gives rise to a homomorphism between their super-Brauer groups (whatever those are). But how do you combine the Brauer groups into a single thing?

    Well, if you have a group homomorphism \(f : G \to H\) you can a make the disjoint union \(G \sqcup H\) into a monoid in a pretty obvious way. This is not quite the collage of the underlying categories of these groups, since it has one object rather than two. But it's related.

    Comment Source:Simon wrote: > One can think (sometimes usefully, sometimes less usefully) of a feasability relation (or profunctor) between preorders as giving rise to a new preorder, known as the **collage**. The underlying set of the collage is the disjoint union \\(X \sqcup Y\\) and on both \\(X\\) and \\(Y\\) the new preorder restricts to the preorders you started with, but for all \\(x \in X\\) and \\(y \in Y\\) you have \\(y\not\le x\\) whilst \\(x\le y\, \iff\ \Phi(x,y)\\). I think it's really great how one can glom together two preorders into a "collage" this way using a feasibility relation... or more generally, glom together two categories using profunctor. But the preorder case is so easy to visualize and like! <img width = "100" src = "http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/mathematical/warning_sign.jpg"> I got interested in collages when thinking about the [10-fold way](https://golem.ph.utexas.edu/category/2014/07/the_tenfold_way_part_2.html) in condensed matter physics. I noticed that it arose from taking the 2-element super-Brauer group of the complex numbers and the 8-element super-Brauer group of the real numbers and glomming them into a single structure. It's easy to check that a field homomorphism like \\(\mathbb{R} \hookrightarrow \mathbb{C}\\) gives rise to a homomorphism between their super-Brauer groups (whatever those are). But how do you combine the Brauer groups into a single thing? Well, if you have a group homomorphism \\(f : G \to H\\) you can a make the disjoint union \\(G \sqcup H\\) into a monoid in a pretty obvious way. This is not quite the collage of the underlying categories of these groups, since it has one object rather than two. But it's related.
  • 11.
    edited July 2018

    Then taking that behavior and extending it over the superposition* of graphs, should give a decent idea of supposition of one category (groupoid) over another. Which like a non disjoint union in type theory requires specifying the overlap.

    • Superposition in the general sense, that is metaphorically physically overlaying one thing on top of another thing.
    Comment Source:Then taking that behavior and extending it over the superposition* of graphs, should give a decent idea of supposition of one category (groupoid) over another. Which like a non disjoint union in type theory requires specifying the overlap. * Superposition in the general sense, that is metaphorically physically overlaying one thing on top of another thing.
  • 12.
    edited July 2018

    John

    Thanks for getting my head back on LOL. Indeed I have trouble knowing what to assume and where exactly I need to end up. Christopher has a nice answer for Puzzle 174 so I will write out Puzzle 173 to practice (hopefully correctly).

    Assume \(f : X \to Y\) is monotone and define \(\Phi\) by

    $$ \Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y .$$ We want to prove \(\Phi\) is a feasibility relation. So, it suffices to show
    1. If \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\) and \(x' \le x\) then \(\Phi(x',y) = \text{true}\).
    2. If \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\) and \(y \le y'\) then \(\Phi(x,y') = \text{true}\).

    So we have at our dispense: $$\Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y $$ $$x' \leq x \;\text{and}\; f(x') \leq f(x)$$ $$y \le y'$$ And we have to show $$\Phi(x',y') = \text{true}$$ Here we go: $$\Phi(x,y) = f(x) \le y $$ $$\rightarrow f(x) \le y' \text{ since } y \le y'$$ $$\rightarrow f(x') \le y' \text{ since } x' \leq x \;\text{and}\; f(x') \leq f(x)$$ $$\Phi(x',y') \text{ by definition of } \Phi $$

    Comment Source:John Thanks for getting my head back on LOL. Indeed I have trouble knowing what to assume and where exactly I need to end up. Christopher has a nice answer for **Puzzle 174** so I will write out **Puzzle 173** to practice (hopefully correctly). > Assume \\(f : X \to Y\\) is monotone and define \\(\Phi\\) by > \[ \Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y .\] > We want to prove \\(\Phi\\) is a feasibility relation. So, it suffices to show > 1. If \\(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\\) and \\(x' \le x\\) then \\(\Phi(x',y) = \text{true}\\). > 2. If \\(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\\) and \\(y \le y'\\) then \\(\Phi(x,y') = \text{true}\\). So we have at our dispense: $$\Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y $$ $$x' \leq x \;\text{and}\; f(x') \leq f(x)$$ $$y \le y'$$ And we have to show $$\Phi(x',y') = \text{true}$$ Here we go: $$\Phi(x,y) = f(x) \le y $$ $$\rightarrow f(x) \le y' \text{ since } y \le y'$$ $$\rightarrow f(x') \le y' \text{ since } x' \leq x \;\text{and}\; f(x') \leq f(x)$$ $$\Phi(x',y') \text{ by definition of } \Phi $$
  • 13.

    Michael - yes, that's good! Great!

    You would need some feedback, and practice to learn how to write up proofs the way mathematicians do. This is math grad students spend so much time doing homeworks full of proofs, and I spend so much time grading these, writing comments in the margin, and showing all the students the 'best' proofs, so they can learn what good examples are like.

    However, you didn't sign up for math grad school, and I'm not being paid to teach this course, so I won't correct the style of your proof. I will just say: you've got the idea right. :)>-

    Comment Source:Michael - yes, that's good! Great! You would need some feedback, and practice to learn how to write up proofs the way mathematicians do. This is math grad students spend so much time doing homeworks full of proofs, and I spend so much time grading these, writing comments in the margin, and showing all the students the 'best' proofs, so they can learn what good examples are like. However, you didn't sign up for math grad school, and I'm not being paid to teach this course, so I won't correct the style of your proof. I will just say: you've got the idea right. :)>-
  • 14.

    Hey Michael,

    To follow up on what John Baez said:

    You would need some feedback, and practice to learn how to write up proofs the way mathematicians do. This is math grad students spend so much time doing homeworks full of proofs, and I spend so much time grading these, writing comments in the margin, and showing all the students the 'best' proofs, so they can learn what good examples are like.

    I've seen some free MOOCs where students grade one another. In this forum, I know I make my fair share of mistakes. Other students kindly point them out, so I have had a lot of chance to improve.

    John gave you a head start on the proof of the puzzle:

    Assume \(f : X \to Y\) is monotone and define \(\Phi\) by

    $$ \Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y .$$ We want to prove \(\Phi\) is a feasibility relation. So, it suffices to show
    1. If \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\) and \(x' \le x\) then \(\Phi(x',y) = \text{true}\).
    2. If \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\) and \(y \le y'\) then \(\Phi(x,y') = \text{true}\).

    Sadly, you can't just show $$\Phi(x',y') = \text{true}$$ You have to show (1) and (2).

    So let's prove (1).

    Proof. Assume (a) \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\) and (b) \(x' \le x\). We must show \(\Phi(x',y) = \text{true}\).

    From (a), we know since \(\Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y\) that:

    $$ f(x) \leq y \tag{c}$$ By (b) and the assumption that \(f\) is monotone, we have

    $$f(x') \le f(x) \tag{d}$$ From (c) and (d) we have by the transitivity of the preorder relation \(\leq\)

    $$f(x') \le y $$ This, along with \(\Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y\), suffices to show \(\Phi(x',y) = \text{true}\) as desired.


    There are many styles of proof.

    TLA+ is a computer proof system. It has been used to analyze software systems at Amazon looking for bugs. The author of TLA+, Leslie Lamport, has some opinions about how proofs should be written. You can read them in How to Write a 21st Century Proof.

    I have done a lot of computer proofs. They are in my opinion, mechanical and boring. But, you can get really good at writing technically correct proofs, since you have the computer to check you.

    But I think proofs are like artwork. If you want to read beautiful proofs, I recommend Proofs from THE BOOK (2013) by Aigner, Ziegler and Hofmann.

    I suspect John Baez feels the same, perhaps he will stop by and make some reading suggestions...

    Comment Source:Hey Michael, To follow up on what John Baez said: > You would need some feedback, and practice to learn how to write up proofs the way mathematicians do. This is math grad students spend so much time doing homeworks full of proofs, and I spend so much time grading these, writing comments in the margin, and showing all the students the 'best' proofs, so they can learn what good examples are like. I've seen some free MOOCs where students grade one another. In this forum, I know I make my fair share of mistakes. Other students kindly point them out, so I have had a lot of chance to improve. John gave you a head start on the proof of the puzzle: > Assume \\(f : X \to Y\\) is monotone and define \\(\Phi\\) by > > \[ \Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y .\] > > We want to prove \\(\Phi\\) is a feasibility relation. So, it suffices to show > > 1. If \\(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\\) and \\(x' \le x\\) then \\(\Phi(x',y) = \text{true}\\). > 2. If \\(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\\) and \\(y \le y'\\) then \\(\Phi(x,y') = \text{true}\\). Sadly, you can't just show $$\Phi(x',y') = \text{true}$$ You have to show (1) and (2). So let's prove (1). **Proof**. Assume (a) \\(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\\) and (b) \\(x' \le x\\). We must show \\(\Phi(x',y) = \text{true}\\). From (a), we know since \\(\Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y\\) that: \[ f(x) \leq y \tag{c}\] By (b) and the assumption that \\(f\\) is monotone, we have \[f(x') \le f(x) \tag{d}\] From (c) and (d) we have by the transitivity of the preorder relation \\(\leq\\) \[f(x') \le y \] This, along with \\(\Phi(x,y) \text{ if and only if } f(x) \le y\\), suffices to show \\(\Phi(x',y) = \text{true}\\) as desired. ---------------------------------- There are many styles of proof. TLA+ is a computer proof system. It has been used to analyze software systems at Amazon looking for bugs. The author of TLA+, Leslie Lamport, has some opinions about how proofs should be written. You can read them in [*How to Write a 21st Century Proof*](https://lamport.azurewebsites.net/pubs/proof.pdf). I have done a lot of computer proofs. They are in my opinion, mechanical and boring. But, you can get really good at writing technically correct proofs, since you have the computer to check you. But I think proofs are like artwork. If you want to read *beautiful* proofs, I recommend [*Proofs from THE BOOK* (2013)](https://www.amazon.com/Proofs-BOOK-Martin-Aigner/dp/3642008550) by Aigner, Ziegler and Hofmann. I suspect John Baez feels the same, perhaps he will stop by and make some reading suggestions...
  • 15.
    edited July 2018

    Matthew - I thought Michael was taking a different approach than the one I suggested: proving that \(\Phi(x',y') = \text{true}\) if \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\), \(x' \le x\) and \(y \le y'\). This uses the 'original' definition of enriched profunctor, which I expanded to a lengthier definition in the theorem in Lecture 56.

    Of course, if this is what Michael was doing, it counts as bad style not to mention it!

    Basically, if a smart mathematician who knows the subject matter doesn't understand your proof, there's probably a way to improve the proof.

    Comment Source:Matthew - I thought Michael was taking a different approach than the one I suggested: proving that \\(\Phi(x',y') = \text{true}\\) if \\(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\\), \\(x' \le x\\) and \\(y \le y'\\). This uses the 'original' definition of enriched profunctor, which I expanded to a lengthier definition in the theorem in [Lecture 56](https://forum.azimuthproject.org/discussion/2280/lecture-56-chapter-4-feasibility-relations/p1). Of course, if this is what Michael was doing, it counts as bad style not to mention it! Basically, if a smart mathematician who knows the subject matter doesn't understand your proof, there's probably a way to improve the proof.
  • 16.

    I thought Michael was taking a different approach than the one I suggested: proving that \(\Phi(x',y') = \text{true}\) if \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\), \(x' \le x\) and \(y \le y'\). This uses the 'original' definition of enriched profunctor, which I expanded to a lengthier definition in the theorem in Lecture 56.

    Ah, sure I see that we can say \(\Phi\) is a feasibility relation if it obeys the axiom:

    $$ x' \le x \text{ and } y \le y' \text{ and } \Phi(x,y) \text{ implies } \Phi(x',y') $$ Michael's proof certainly works, I was just thrown off because I had assumed he was going to prove parts (1) and (2) like you outlined. My mistake!

    Comment Source:> I thought Michael was taking a different approach than the one I suggested: proving that \\(\Phi(x',y') = \text{true}\\) if \\(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\\), \\(x' \le x\\) and \\(y \le y'\\). This uses the 'original' definition of enriched profunctor, which I expanded to a lengthier definition in the theorem in [Lecture 56](https://forum.azimuthproject.org/discussion/2280/lecture-56-chapter-4-feasibility-relations/p1). Ah, sure I see that we can say \\(\Phi\\) is a feasibility relation if it obeys the axiom: \[ x' \le x \text{ and } y \le y' \text{ and } \Phi(x,y) \text{ implies } \Phi(x',y') \] Michael's proof certainly works, I was just thrown off because I had assumed he was going to prove parts (1) and (2) like you outlined. My mistake!
  • 17.
    edited July 2018

    ... but also his mistake, because he make it sound like he was going to do X, and then he did Y.

    Ideally, a proof is an attempt at extremely clear communication. Most proofs don't live up to that standard, though! image

    Comment Source:... but also his mistake, because he make it sound like he was going to do X, and then he did Y. Ideally, a proof is an attempt at extremely clear communication. Most proofs don't live up to that standard, though! <img src = "http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/emoticons/tongue2.gif">
  • 18.
    edited July 2018

    John and Matthew

    Wow thanks for the correction and tips! I am truly grateful!

    Clearly I wasn't being clear in my communication and I think John is giving me the benefit of the doubt in that I knew what I was doing LOL. I was trying to figure out what to assume and what to prove but once I did, I apparently ended up skipping steps and went in a different direction! In my mind after reading Christopher's answer, I realized that you can do that in one step like John said in the end of his comment 9 and pretty much rewrote what Christopher did in terms of this puzzle while making sure I was only using the assumptions I made. Being a newby, I shouldn't have skipped steps and should have done what Matthew did... or at least clearly stated which direction I was going to take as John pointed out...

    Thanks for the references Matthew. I will definitely try to read through and hopefully one day I can become fluent speaker of this beautiful language!

    Comment Source:John and Matthew Wow thanks for the correction and tips! I am truly grateful! Clearly I wasn't being clear in my communication and I think John is giving me the benefit of the doubt in that I knew what I was doing LOL. I was trying to figure out what to assume and what to prove but once I did, I apparently ended up skipping steps and went in a different direction! In my mind after reading Christopher's answer, I realized that you can do that in one step like John said in the end of his [comment 9](https://forum.azimuthproject.org/discussion/comment/19974/#Comment_19974) and pretty much rewrote what Christopher did in terms of this puzzle while making sure I was only using the assumptions I made. Being a newby, I shouldn't have skipped steps and should have done what Matthew did... or at least clearly stated which direction I was going to take as John pointed out... Thanks for the references Matthew. I will definitely try to read through and hopefully one day I can become fluent speaker of this beautiful language!
  • 19.

    I have two small questions:

    1 - In the appealing flight analogy:

    We can think of the arrows in our Hasse diagrams as one-way streets in two cities, \(X\) and \(Y\). And we can think of the blue dashed arrows as one-way plane flights from cities in \(X\) to cities in \(Y\). Then \(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\) if we can get from \(x \in X\) to \(y \in Y\) using any combination of streets and plane flights!

    Should "from cities in \(X\) to cities in \(Y\)" be "from streets in \(X\) to streets in \(Y\)" instead (as \(X,Y\) are already cities themselves)?

    2 - In Puzzle 174:

    Puzzle 174. Suppose \(g: Y \to X \) is a monotone function from \(X\) to \(Y\)...

    Should this be a function from \(Y\) to \(X\) instead?

    Comment Source:I have two small questions: 1 - In the appealing flight analogy: >We can think of the arrows in our Hasse diagrams as _one-way streets_ in two cities, \\(X\\) and \\(Y\\). And we can think of the blue dashed arrows as _one-way plane flights_ from cities in \\(X\\) to cities in \\(Y\\). Then \\(\Phi(x,y) = \text{true}\\) if we can get from \\(x \in X\\) to \\(y \in Y\\) _using any combination of streets and plane flights!_ Should "from cities in \\(X\\) to cities in \\(Y\\)" be "from streets in \\(X\\) to streets in \\(Y\\)" instead (as \\(X,Y\\) are already cities themselves)? 2 - In **Puzzle 174**: >**Puzzle 174.** Suppose \\(g: Y \to X \\) is a monotone function from \\(X\\) to \\(Y\\)... Should this be a function from \\(Y\\) to \\(X\\) instead?
  • 20.

    Julio - I meant for \(X\) and \(Y\) to be countries, \(x \in X\) to be a city in the country \(X\), and \(y \in Y\) to be a city in the country \(Y\).

    So, just one word in my description was wrong, and I'll fix it now. Thanks for catching it!

    And yes, you're right about Puzzle 174, too.

    Comment Source:Julio - I meant for \\(X\\) and \\(Y\\) to be countries, \\(x \in X\\) to be a city in the country \\(X\\), and \\(y \in Y\\) to be a city in the country \\(Y\\). So, just one word in my description was wrong, and I'll fix it now. Thanks for catching it! And yes, you're right about Puzzle 174, too.
  • 21.

    @John Cool, thanks for the clarification! :-)

    By the way, is there any way to efficiently "@" members in this forum? Sometimes I miss replies targeted at me because I don't receive notifications and forget to follow up on all my comments... XD

    Comment Source:@John Cool, thanks for the clarification! :-) By the way, is there any way to efficiently "@" members in this forum? Sometimes I miss replies targeted at me because I don't receive notifications and forget to follow up on all my comments... XD
Sign In or Register to comment.